Tuesday, November 19, 2019
Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics Essay Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 1000 words
Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics - Essay Example Examples of such emotions can be lust, greed, anger, jealousy, hatred, joy, and-in some cases- even love. However a ââ¬Å"continentâ⬠person is able to resist the pressure of such emotions. He is able to dutifully abide by the path that reason prescribes, even if in reality he has no desire for doing so. This dutiful adherence to goodness is not just applicable to cases where the ââ¬Ëgoodââ¬â¢ course of action has been determined by a personââ¬â¢s own intellectual and rational faculties. It can also apply to cases where ââ¬Ëgoodââ¬â¢ has been determined and prescribed by society. Dutiful, albeit passive and thoughtless, adherence to ethical norms can also be called ââ¬Å"continenceâ⬠. An ââ¬Å"incontinentâ⬠person (the Greek word is akratà ªs), on the other hand, is one who succumbs to the pressures of his desires and emotions and violates what in his own opinion is the demand of reason. The incontinent person lacks mastery of feelings. However, Aristotle maintained that ââ¬Å"incontinenceâ⬠is quite distinct from ââ¬Å"evilâ⬠. The ââ¬Å"evilâ⬠are those who believe that virtues (such as justice, temperance and truthfulness) are useless, and are not to be pursued at all. While the ââ¬Å"incontinentâ⬠person fails to pursue ââ¬Ëgoodââ¬â¢ out of a ââ¬Ëweakness of willââ¬â¢, the evil do not even attempt to be virtuous. In other words the evil do not reach the conclusion that the virtuous course of action is rational; which seems, more or less, like a defect in their intelligence, or their rational faculties. He refers to the evil as kakos or as phaulos. It is important to note that even though the ââ¬Å"incontinentâ⬠a re removed from acting in a virtuous manner, they do acknowledge a duty of doing so. Hence, according to Aristotle, their situation is not hopeless (incontinence isnââ¬â¢t vicious). Here one might raise the concern that if the ââ¬Å"incontinentâ⬠succumb to the inexorable counter-pressure of their desires and their emotions; then their actions are involuntary. And since, as the well known dictum suggests, ââ¬Ëoughtââ¬â¢ implies ââ¬Ëcanââ¬â¢, we can safely assume that the ââ¬Å"incontinentâ⬠arenââ¬â¢t morally responsible for their seemingly reprehensible actions. However, Aristotleââ¬â¢s notion of ââ¬Å"voluntaryâ⬠(Book 3, Chapter 1) is entirely negative. An action is voluntary in two conditions. The first condition is the absence of any sort of ââ¬Ëcompulsionââ¬â¢ toward the performance of the action, and the second condition is the absence of ââ¬Ëignoranceââ¬â¢ about the harmful consequences of the action. Note that ââ¬Ëcompul sionââ¬â¢ in used here only in the sense of being compelled by an external force (a force that lies outside the agent). And since desires and emotions lie within a person, therefore when an ââ¬Å"incontinentâ⬠person succumbs to the pressure of his desires he can not be said to be acting involuntarily. It is clear that a person will act in ways that are ââ¬Ëgoodââ¬â¢ if he is ââ¬Å"continentâ⬠, and resists the irrational appetites that haunt him. However, according to Aristotle, the life of such a person is not virtuous. Aristotle believes that true ââ¬Ëvirtueââ¬â¢ and goodness are quite distinct from both continence and incontinence. In fact, Aristotle regards ââ¬Ëcontinenceââ¬â¢, ââ¬Ëincontinenceââ¬â¢ and ââ¬Ë
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.